Kevin Vanhoozer edits a booked titled Nothing Greater, Nothing Better. It is a series of articles
covering contemporary issues on the love of God. I was particularly struck by a
chapter in the book by Gary Badcock, titled “The Concept of Love: Divine and
Human.”
Badcock discusses to two attempts to make sense of God’s
ability to love humans. The first is from Plato. Plato described love as “born
of need” (Vanhoozer, 31). So, according to Plato’s view, one person loves
another person because they need affection. One loves wisdom because they have
some foolishness in them (31-32). So, the gods, to Plato, cannot love because
they do not have needs. The other attempt at describing God’s love comes from
Anders Nygren. Nygren, in reaction to Plato, describes God’s love as the agape love that is “spontaneous and
uncaused,” “indifferent to human merit” (33). So, according to Nygren, God sees
nothing loveable in humans, but loves them anyway because he is God.
Badcock tries to find a kind of middle ground between these
two. I do find his answer striking, but unsatisfying. I will try to deal with
two important statements in Badcock’s reconciliation.
First, in reaction to Nygren’s view of man’s depravity, that
“he [God] is unable to see any good remaining with human nature after the fall”
(35), Badcock argues that “he [Nygren] represents an unduly pessimistic view of
human nature and an inadequate doctrine of sin” (35). In response he says, “It
is the love of God for the person that is all-important, the divine love that
recognizes the goodness or potential for goodness buried deep beneath the mound
of perceived unloveliness” (36).
Without saying it, it seems that Badcock is using Nygren as
a kind of caricature for what is typically the Reformed view of total depravity.
Like the liberal media loves reporting stories of Westburo Baptist church and
other crazies, I come across a surprising amount of writers and speakers who
tend to cite extreme versions of Calvinist doctrines and use it to knock down
what most Calvinists actually say. What
I am saying is that Badcock’s choice of Nygren over a more classic approach,
like Augustine, is suspect. He seems to
be setting up a kind of legal straw man. It’s above the belt, but it’s still a
gut-check.
I agree with Badcock that the choice between Plato’s view
and Nygren’s view is a false dilemma. I sit in the middle with him. He seems to
sit a bit closer to Plato and I seem closer to Nygren. I am also arguing,
however, that the rest of the Reformed community seems closer to me than to
Nygren.
I haven’t read any Reformed theologians who would claim that
there is not “any good remaining within human nature after the fall.” Reformed
theology typically champions common grace and the imago Dei. There is certainly a great worth to human beings that
God is jealous to restore. That remaining good, however, is not the motivation
of God’s love. He needs no motivation. So, I think Reformed theology has a
medium between these views that is not guilty of the same overstatements as
Nygren.
The second statement from Badcock that struck me is that
“God is affected by the world-or at
the very least he chooses to be so-which is no more than to say that it matters
to him, that he loves it” (46).
First, I want to point out some a presupposition to
Badcock’s thinking. This statement is assuming that in order for love to exist,
it must be affected by the one being loved. Not being affected implies
“indifference” (46). It matters to me what Badcock means by “affected.” He isn’t,
however, clear on this. If it merely means that God relates, responds, feels,
and cares, I am not concerned. If he believes that God is “affected” in a way
that implies humans do things that God didn’t expect and that have an impact on
God’s experience as God, that is more concerning. He seems to step into this
line of thinking when he says, “both positions err in not recognizing that the
existence of the world adds something to God’s experience” (46).
While I think that Badcock raises some striking problems, I
do not think we need to find answers to them in God’s being affected by humans
in the way Badcock is describing. I think we need only look to the Trinity. In
Jn. 10:17, Jesus states that the Father loves him. It seems reasonable to
assume that Persons of the Trinity have loved each other from all eternity.
From this, I would argue, that God’s intra-Trinitarian love for himself propels
his love for humanity. His love for himself need not be affected by humans to
be legitimate. He has had enough love pouring from his own being from all
eternity that it does not seem to lesson his love to say that it is completely
self-provoked. That is why I can hold to a Calvinistic view of human depravity are
and have no problem seeing God’s love as actual love. Because, when the Father sees his church, he sees
Christ.
No comments:
Post a Comment